The experiments of the
physiologist Benjamin Libet are famous for their contribution to the free
will/determinism debate to the extent that in popular imagination they are
often believed to have disproved the existence of free will.
The most important study was Libet, B.,
Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W. & Pearl, D. K., Brain, 106, (1983), pp. 623-642. Here motor cortical activity
was measured using EMG (scalp electrodes) and was used to isolate the pattern
associated with the moving of a hand, which was termed the ‘readiness
potential’. Individually tested subjects were asked to sit down and after how
ever long they liked to spontaneously move a hand. Simultaneously they were to
remember the time at which they decided to move the hand.
Libet’s tests discovered readiness potential
an average of 1/5 second before the subject was aware of making the choice. The
spread had an upper limit of 1/2 second. Among others who have replicated the
experiment, apparently one study reported an average readiness potential of 1
1/4 seconds.
So here’s why it doesn’t disprove free will:
1. The experiment presupposes a kind of naïve view of
free will (as a sort of ‘ghost in the machine’). Its conclusions are only
shocking because we assume that free will requires that the conscious
experience of having made a decision comes first, and that this somehow causes
the brain activity, but there is no reason why that should have to be the case.
2. It seems therefore to commit the post
hoc ergo
propter hoc fallacy (the assumption that if something comes
before an event it is the cause of the event). It’s almost certain that the
brain activity is a cause of the action, but
a cause does not equate to the cause. That
something is caused (in the sense of being influenced by at least one cause)
doesn’t preclude an overlapping network of causes that may ultimately be
controlled by the willpower of the agent, a willpower itself not caused by
random, unchosen prior events.
3. You’d be forgiven for assuming that Libet, as an
esteemed scientist, accounted for false positives. That is, that
brain activity didn’t build up when the subject did not move their hand. But in
fact he admitted that his experiments told us nothing about what he called
‘free won't’- our ability to resist impulses. But surely this faculty is at
least as important to our freedom as one of producing spontaneous choices?
Libet’s work is no longer unique, but more
recent studies have problems with false positives too. The most influential
report today is: Soon, C. S., Brass, M., Heinze, H.-J., & Haynes, J.
D., Nature Neuroscience, 11, (2008), pp. 543-545. The study, conducted
by John Dyllan Haynes, was based on a different experiment and found an
average gap of 7 seconds, with 10 seconds as the upper limit of the spread.
This is a lot more significant, but the brain activity only correlated with the
relevant behaviours at a level of 10% above chance. Or in other words, the
predictions had only 60%
accuracy at best.
4. The amounts of time we are dealing with here are so
small that there is a high margin for error, given that, in Libet’s
experiments, the subject needs time to realise they have to record the time
and this isn’t a task humans are going to be extremely accurate at. This isn’t
much of a problem for Haynes’ experiments, however. They are more accurate
because instead of the EMG they use fMRI scanning which picks up
the brain activity in more specific detail.
5. It makes perfect sense that if we were told that in
the near future we were going to have to make a decision that our brain would
subconsciously prepare for that decision. A more accurate experiment would
involve a test subject unaware of the choice they are going to make.
6. The experiment’s results can only be generalised to
incredibly simple decisions. In a further study, Haynes has made an improvement
here, by testing subjects with mathematical problems, but this is still a world
away from important examples of free choice, such as choosing who to marry.
Just because it would be impossible to set up an experiment to test these sorts
of things doesn’t mean that we can jump to conclusions.
7. We need to keep a clear distinction between the act
of willing something (volition) and the process of deliberation. Even if we do
not freely will any of our actions in a
direct sense that would not require that we lack free will in the relevant
sense of having control over our actions. This is because we still may well be
able to deliberate with a significant degree of freedom. And even if these
deliberations partly take place in brain activity that is preconscious, this
would not mean that we were not responsible for how those deliberations played out,
since the brain structures that facilitate them have been moulded by
the habits we’ve formed.
To move in the direction of finishing up,
let’s note some general problems in this debate:
8. Here is an excellent quote from Eddy Nahmias: “One reason it is easy to move from the assumption that
neural processes cause behaviour to the presumption that consciousness does nothing
is that neuroscience still lacks a theory to explain how certain types of brain
processes are the basis of conscious or rational mental processes. Without such
a story in place, it is easy to assume that neuroscientific explanations
supersede and bypass explanations in terms of conscious and rational
processes.”
9. There’s a somewhat complicated philosophical reason why we
should always be very weary of a purported proof of determinism. Namely, even
if determinism were true, statements about future events could not be factually expressed
by anyone. For if they were, these expressions would have a strong potential to
influence future events so as to thwart the veridical status of the statements.
10. In our personal experience we do make free choices, even
grudgingly when we don’t want to do something. We experience instances of
having more or less control (e.g. with fatigue and drugs) implying that we do
have control. This view of reality ‘from the inside’ might be subjective, but
not in the sense of being a matter of opinion- indeed it is objective in the
sense that this information would have been there whether we studied it or not.
In any case this is more direct knowledge of reality than that gained by
inductive experiment and therefore it is reasonable to regard it as
authoritative.
This article was provided and written by Peter Hardy a member of our UK Apologetics Facebook group. You can follow Peter on Twitter @vibrantbliss
This article was provided and written by Peter Hardy a member of our UK Apologetics Facebook group. You can follow Peter on Twitter @vibrantbliss
No comments:
Post a Comment